\
  The most prestigious law school admissions discussion board in the world.
BackRefresh Options Favorite

On niggers (Karlstack)

The issue of disproportionate crime rates among niggers in t...
Karlstack (Retired)
  10/08/24
...
Reyn Spooner
  10/08/24
why can't you pretend to be someone else?
....,.,.,,,.,....,.......,........
  10/08/24
?
Karlstack (Retired)
  10/08/24
why would karlstack want to pretend to be someone else?
cock of michael obama
  10/08/24
...
hot joe
  10/08/24
...
cock of michael obama
  10/08/24
Wow. Subscribed.
Karlstack (LLM slop)
  10/08/24


Poast new message in this thread



Reply Favorite

Date: October 8th, 2024 7:13 AM
Author: Karlstack (Retired)

The issue of disproportionate crime rates among niggers in the United States is one fraught with controversy, not least because it exposes a deeply polarized interpretive rift between sociological and biological explanations. For decades, the dominant liberal consensus has attributed these disparities solely to the deleterious effects of systemic racism, socio-economic inequality, and cultural marginalization. In this narrative, crime is viewed not as a moral failing but as a consequence of disenfranchisement—an understandable reaction to generations of poverty, exclusion, and state-sanctioned discrimination. Yet, this perspective, pervasive as it is, evades confronting more unsettling possibilities that might transcend mere environmental factors. Namely, it skirts around the uncomfortable notion that genetic predispositions could contribute to these observed patterns, a hypothesis that has been bolstered by decades of adoption and twin studies, however unpalatable it may be to modern sensibilities.

Even if one accepts that centuries of oppression and deprivation have left indelible marks on the socio-cultural fabric of African American communities, the question arises: does this explanation alone suffice? If systemic racism were the only relevant variable, one would expect the elevation in crime rates to dissipate as social policies became more inclusive and economic prospects improved. Yet, despite monumental shifts in civil rights legislation, affirmative action, and anti-discrimination laws, the disparity persists. Moreover, immigrant communities from similarly deprived backgrounds often experience rapid upward mobility, eschewing crime and achieving educational and professional success within a single generation. Could it be, then, that something deeper is at play?

A more dispassionate examination of the evidence would have to consider genetic influences alongside socio-cultural determinants. Adoption studies—such as those conducted in the 1980s by the University of Colorado and in Denmark—consistently show that African American children adopted into affluent white families display higher rates of delinquency than their white counterparts raised in the same environments. These findings, controversial as they are, suggest that shared environment is not the only factor. Twin studies further complicate the picture, indicating that criminal behavior is moderately heritable, with a heritability coefficient for antisocial behavior hovering around 0.50. If genetic components play such a significant role, the implications are profound and unsettling.

This is not to say that genes are destiny—far from it. Rather, genetic predispositions interact with environmental stimuli in complex, non-linear ways. A higher propensity for impulsivity, risk-taking, or aggression, for example, does not manifest uniformly across all contexts. In environments characterized by strong social norms, robust familial structures, and economic stability, such predispositions can be channeled productively, or at least contained. But in urban neighborhoods marked by a paucity of economic opportunities, broken family systems, and a palpable sense of despair, these traits may translate more readily into violent or criminal behavior. Thus, the interplay between nature and nurture becomes a critical, if uncomfortable, focal point for understanding why certain communities exhibit higher crime rates, even when stripped of the traditional socio-economic explanations.

The liberal sociological view also falters in its monolithic portrayal of African American crime as an entirely rational response to deprivation. It assumes that external factors alone drive behavior, overlooking the empirical reality that certain types of crime—such as violent offenses—occur at elevated rates even in Black middle-class and upper-middle-class neighborhoods. The 2006 study by criminologists Peterson and Krivo found that majority-Black high-income areas still experienced significantly more violent crime than majority-white low-income areas. This directly contradicts the notion that socio-economic conditions alone are decisive and suggests that other variables—potentially cultural, or even biological—may be exerting a greater influence than many are willing to acknowledge.

But what if the standard narratives are wrong? What if the repeated attempts to explain away these disparities through the rubric of socio-economic deprivation, state overreach, or cultural decay are themselves symptomatic of an ideological blindness? It is almost as if the establishment, unwilling to countenance the uncomfortable truths emerging from behavioral genetics and heritability studies, insists on stretching a thin veil of social justice rhetoric over what may be far deeper, more intractable realities. If adoption studies show that African American children raised in affluent white families are still more likely to engage in delinquent behavior, what does this say about the supposed power of environment to rectify these disparities? Is it not possible that by ignoring potential genetic factors, liberal theorists are merely doubling down on a failed experiment, sacrificing intellectual honesty on the altar of political expediency?

None of this is to suggest that environmental factors are irrelevant—they are unquestionably significant. Systemic discrimination, concentrated poverty, and educational neglect are potent catalysts that amplify whatever innate vulnerabilities may exist. But to argue that these are the sole factors is to willfully disregard the growing body of evidence from behavioral genetics, which suggests that individual differences in temperament, impulse control, and aggression are not uniformly distributed across populations. Indeed, such an omission is not merely an academic oversight but a deliberate evasion, rooted more in ideological dogmatism than in a genuine pursuit of truth.

Critics will, of course, accuse this line of inquiry of being reductive, even racist. They will insist that acknowledging biological differences is tantamount to excusing racism or giving up on the project of equality. But the truth, however unpleasant, is that a rational discourse must follow the evidence wherever it leads. If the liberal narrative cannot explain why Black crime rates remain stubbornly elevated even in favorable conditions, then we must be willing to entertain alternative hypotheses, however much they might disrupt the comfortable orthodoxies of our time.

In the end, the real tragedy lies not in acknowledging the complexity of human behavior, but in refusing to do so. By clinging to overly simplistic, purely socio-cultural explanations, we condemn ourselves to policy failures that do nothing to alleviate the suffering of those trapped in high-crime communities. If there is a genetic component at play, then denying it is not a form of benevolence or respect—it is, in fact, a profound disservice, an abrogation of our duty to understand and, if possible, ameliorate the root causes of human behavior. The conversation must evolve beyond the binary of environment versus biology and instead grapple with the uncomfortable reality that it is both, intertwined in ways that defy easy categorization. Only then can we hope to devise solutions that address the full spectrum of factors shaping human life, however inconvenient they may be.

Beyond the troubling disparities in crime rates, the educational achievement gap between African Americans and other ethnic groups in the United States presents an equally disconcerting dilemma. For decades, efforts to close this gap through a variety of interventions—affirmative action, increased funding for public schools, and diversity initiatives—have failed to produce substantial change. Once again, the standard liberal narrative has ascribed this phenomenon entirely to socio-economic inequality, systemic racism, and the lingering effects of historical injustice. While these explanations hold some merit, they struggle to account for why other minority groups—often with similar or even greater historical disadvantages—are able to outperform African Americans both academically and professionally. The question, then, is whether the factors commonly cited as primary causes of underachievement truly suffice, or whether we must consider more contentious explanations, including genetic predispositions, differences in cognitive ability, or distinct cultural orientations toward education and achievement.

For context, the disparity in academic performance is both pronounced and pervasive. On virtually every standardized measure—whether it be the SAT, ACT, or state-administered assessments—African American students score significantly lower on average than their white and Asian peers. The gap is persistent even after controlling for socio-economic status, parental education, and school quality. In mathematics, reading, and science, African American students trail behind by as much as 1.0 to 1.5 standard deviations, a difference that translates into a roughly 10-15 IQ point gap when measured on psychometric scales. This disparity only widens as students progress through the education system, manifesting not only in lower high school graduation rates but also in decreased college enrollment and completion rates. Perhaps most tellingly, African Americans are markedly underrepresented in the most challenging academic fields, such as engineering, physics, and mathematics, where the cognitive demands are highest and the curve is steepest.

In Engineering specifically, the gulf is stark. Despite decades of targeted outreach, scholarship programs, and professional support, African Americans remain dramatically underrepresented in this and other STEM (Science, Technology, Engineering, Mathematics) fields. The National Science Foundation (NSF) data reveals that Black Americans comprise less than 4% of the engineering workforce, a number that has barely budged in over a decade. Even within the context of academic settings, African American students often struggle to keep pace with their peers, leading to higher dropout rates in rigorous STEM programs and a pronounced reluctance to enter these demanding fields. This discrepancy cannot be fully explained by economic deprivation or lack of resources; for example, Asian Americans, despite having suffered historical discrimination and often coming from lower-income, non-English-speaking immigrant families, are vastly overrepresented in engineering and the sciences. Thus, the simple equation of "poverty = underachievement" fails to account for the resilience and overperformance of other groups under similarly adverse conditions.

Could it be, then, that underlying cognitive differences contribute to this gap? Twin and adoption studies once again complicate the picture. Research has shown that IQ is highly heritable, with a heritability coefficient ranging from 0.60 to 0.80 in adulthood. Moreover, the IQ distribution for African Americans is shifted downward relative to that of whites and Asians, with a median around 85 compared to 100 for whites and 105-110 for Asians. This variance in cognitive ability, uncomfortable as it may be to acknowledge, correlates strongly with academic achievement and professional success in fields that demand high levels of abstraction, complex problem-solving, and mathematical reasoning. If IQ is indeed a significant predictor of educational and occupational outcomes—and most studies suggest that it is—then no amount of socio-cultural intervention alone can fully equalize outcomes across groups.

Critics will immediately cry foul at this suggestion, accusing it of veiled eugenics or scientific racism. But the issue is not whether genetic differences exist—they undeniably do, both within and between populations—but rather how much these differences matter in explaining complex behaviors and outcomes. Even a modest genetic influence on cognitive ability would imply that, in aggregate, certain populations will tend to have fewer individuals at the upper end of the intelligence distribution. And if elite academic and professional fields such as engineering or theoretical physics draw almost exclusively from the top decile of cognitive ability, then one would naturally expect lower representation from groups with fewer individuals in that decile, regardless of socio-cultural factors. This hypothesis, though distasteful to modern egalitarian sensibilities, is consistent with the empirical data, which shows persistent gaps even in environments where African Americans are afforded every conceivable advantage.

None of this, of course, is to say that niggers are inherently incapable of achieving success in challenging fields. Rather, the point is that the existing disparities are unlikely to be remedied by superficial fixes—be they affirmative action, “equity-based” curriculum changes, or endless rounds of diversity training. Such initiatives, while politically expedient, fail to address the root causes of underachievement. At best, they provide temporary boosts in representation through lowered standards or race-based admissions policies, which do little more than shuffle candidates between institutions. In some cases, they may even exacerbate the problem by placing students into environments where they are ill-prepared to compete, resulting in the so-called "mismatch effect," wherein minority students admitted under lower standards are more likely to drop out or switch to less demanding majors.

The uncomfortable truth, then, is that closing the achievement gap may require acknowledging that not all disparities are solely the product of discrimination or socio-economic deprivation. If genetic predispositions contribute even modestly to group differences in cognitive ability, then we must recalibrate our expectations accordingly. This does not mean abandoning efforts to uplift disadvantaged communities or ensure equal opportunity, but it does mean recognizing that equal outcomes may never be attainable without compromising the standards that define excellence in fields like engineering and mathematics. To continue insisting that African Americans should be equally represented in these high-achievement domains, without accounting for differences in aptitude, is to set them up for perpetual failure and frustration.

Moreover, there is the often-ignored question of cultural orientation toward education and intellectual achievement. Historically, African American communities have prioritized athletic and artistic success over academic distinction, with intellectual achievement sometimes derided as "acting white." This anti-intellectual culture, coupled with a valorization of physical prowess and street credibility, creates an environment that is fundamentally hostile to the pursuit of excellence in rigorous academic fields. Even where cognitive ability is high, a culture that does not celebrate or support intellectual effort will produce fewer engineers, scientists, and mathematicians. By contrast, Asian American communities, despite facing their own set of challenges, have fostered a culture of intense academic competition and familial pressure to excel, resulting in a disproportionate number of high-achievers in STEM fields. To ignore the cultural component is to misunderstand the full scope of the problem.

Ultimately, the achievement gap in education and professional fields like Engineering is not merely a statistical anomaly to be smoothed over by policy tweaks. It is a manifestation of deeper, more enduring differences—both cultural and, potentially, biological—that no amount of wishful thinking or social Engineering can erase. We can continue to paper over these gaps with euphemisms and platitudes, or we can confront the reality that true equality, in terms of outcomes, may never be possible. Only by facing these hard truths can we begin to formulate policies that respect the complexities of human variation rather than flatten them into an unrealistic ideal of universal parity. Anything less is not just intellectually dishonest, but ultimately detrimental to those it purports to help.



(http://www.autoadmit.com/thread.php?thread_id=5608350&forum_id=2\u0026mark_id=5310895",#48176174)



Reply Favorite

Date: October 8th, 2024 7:16 AM
Author: Reyn Spooner



(http://www.autoadmit.com/thread.php?thread_id=5608350&forum_id=2\u0026mark_id=5310895",#48176176)



Reply Favorite

Date: October 8th, 2024 7:16 AM
Author: ....,.,.,,,.,....,.......,........


why can't you pretend to be someone else?

(http://www.autoadmit.com/thread.php?thread_id=5608350&forum_id=2\u0026mark_id=5310895",#48176177)



Reply Favorite

Date: October 8th, 2024 7:19 AM
Author: Karlstack (Retired)

?

(http://www.autoadmit.com/thread.php?thread_id=5608350&forum_id=2\u0026mark_id=5310895",#48176181)



Reply Favorite

Date: October 8th, 2024 9:46 AM
Author: cock of michael obama

why would karlstack want to pretend to be someone else?

(http://www.autoadmit.com/thread.php?thread_id=5608350&forum_id=2\u0026mark_id=5310895",#48176486)



Reply Favorite

Date: October 8th, 2024 9:43 AM
Author: hot joe



(http://www.autoadmit.com/thread.php?thread_id=5608350&forum_id=2\u0026mark_id=5310895",#48176477)



Reply Favorite

Date: October 8th, 2024 10:22 AM
Author: cock of michael obama



(http://www.autoadmit.com/thread.php?thread_id=5608350&forum_id=2\u0026mark_id=5310895",#48176607)



Reply Favorite

Date: October 8th, 2024 10:49 AM
Author: Karlstack (LLM slop)

Wow. Subscribed.

(http://www.autoadmit.com/thread.php?thread_id=5608350&forum_id=2\u0026mark_id=5310895",#48176694)